Google+

Bench Memos

NRO’s home for judicial news and analysis.

This Day in Liberal Judicial Activism—May 17



Text  



1954—In Brown v. Board of Education, a unanimous Supreme Court abandons available originalist justifications for its ruling that state-segregated schools violate the Equal Protection Clause—justifications that would have been far weightier, and commanded far more public respect, than its own makeshift reliance on contemporaneous psychological research of dubious relevance. Contrary to conventional understanding, the Court declines to revisit its notorious 1896 ruling in Plessy v. Ferguson and instead limits itself to the question whether the separate-but-equal rule of Plessy “should be held inapplicable to public education.”

1993—Tennessee chief justice Lyle Reid and justice Martha Craig Daughtrey dispute the ruling by the Tennessee supreme court in State v. Marshall that obscenity is not protected speech under the Tennessee constitution. The majority’s ruling, they extravagantly contend, hands “the right most essential to personal dignity and democratic government, the freedom of expression, … into the willing grasp of the censor.”

Daughtrey will be appointed by President Clinton to the Sixth Circuit later in 1993.

2013—Crackheaded, indeed. In United States v. Blewett, Sixth Circuit judge Gilbert S. Merritt Jr., joined by fellow Carter appointee Boyce F. Martin Jr., holds that the more lenient sentences of the Fair Sentencing Act of 2010 apply to crack-cocaine offenders who were sentenced before the Act’s effective date.

Merritt purports to recognize that “there is no equal protection violation without discriminatory intent,” and he acknowledges that when the 100-to-1 crack statute was adopted in 1986, “there was no intent or design to discriminate on a racial basis.” But he contends that the knowledge gained since 1986 about the disparate impact of the original minimums on blacks means that continued enforcement of those sentences is intentional discrimination.

Under Merritt’s illogic, once it becomes known that a law has a (constitutionally permissible) racially disparate impact, the maintenance of that law would suddenly be transformed into intentional discrimination. As Clinton appointee Ronald Lee Gilman observes in dissent, there is no support for such a proposition.

Some six months later, by a disturbingly close 10-7 vote, the en banc Sixth Circuit will reject Merritt’s reasoning. As Judge Jeffrey Sutton nicely sums it up in his majority opinion, the legal question is simple:

“Consistent with a 142-year-old congressional presumption against applying reductions in criminal penalties to those already sentenced, 1 U.S.C. § 109, consistent with the views of all nine Justices and all of the litigants in Dorsey v. United States (2012), consistent with the decisions of every other court of appeals in the country, and consistent with dozens of our own decisions, we hold that the Act does not retroactively undo final sentences.”

Judges (and Others) Behaving Badly



Text  



The National Law Journal has an article about efforts being made to increase the number of minority law clerks for judges. It’s clear enough that these efforts are not limited to preventing discrimination, of course; rather, race is to be weighed.

I won’t belabor the moral problems raised by hiring with an eye on skin color, but I think it is worth mentioning that this is illegal. 

For starters, judges are state actors, as are government agencies, so there are constitutional problems with their involvement in these efforts. To the extent that nonprofits, also mentioned in the article, are involved, they are likewise prohibited from engaging in racial discrimination by Title VI of the 1964 Civil Rights Act if they get any federal money. Of course, the Supreme Court in its wisdom has interpreted Title VI and the Constitution to allow racial preferences in university admissions, but this “diversity” rationale has never been recognized by the Court in the employment context. 

Most important, Title VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act has never had a “diversity” exception carved out of it by the federal courts, and it prohibits racial discrimination by federal and state employers, which would include judges. What’s more, it bans discrimination by any “employment agency,” which it defines as “any person regularly undertaking with or without compensation to procure employees for an employer or to procure for employees opportunities to work for an employer and includes the agent of such person,” which would cover the nonprofits and others discussed in the National Law Journal article.

To paraphrase Luke 4:23, “Judge, sue thyself.”

ADVERTISEMENT

This Day in Liberal Judicial Activism—May 16



Text  



2011—In United States v. C.R., senior federal district judge Jack B. Weinstein issues a 349-page opinion (with an additional 50+ pages of appendices) holding that the Eighth Amendment prohibits applying the statutory minimum five-year term of imprisonment to a youthful defendant who pleaded guilty to one count of distributing child pornography. Here’s how criminal-procedure expert Orin Kerr prefaces his discussion of the ruling:

“There are a lot of debates about ‘judicial activism’ in which some question whether the term has real meaning. Fortunately, there is always Jack Weinstein, whose activism is so over-the-top that it easily quiets the debates.”

Some two years later, a Second Circuit panel will unanimously reverse Weinstein’s ruling.

Misleading and Dishonest Reporting from Jeffrey Toobin



Text  



Over at The New Yorker’s blog, Jeffrey Toobin has a ridiculous post that distorts the facts and repeats paranoid conspiracy theories. Toobin’s beef is with the Federalist Society, the venerable educational organization that provides a forum for discussion of the most important conservative and libertarian legal issues, and Chuck Cooper, one of 22 speakers at its Second Annual Executive Branch Review Conference.

As Toobin concedes, events sponsored by the Federalist Society feature “high-level intellectual combat” between panelists from right and left. Having attended multiple prior conferences, which invariably offer excellent panel discussions (and usually offer CLE credit), I can tell you that the liberal and progressive speakers almost uniformly praise the Federalist Society for sponsoring a robust exchange of ideas and open debate among a wide variety of views.

Since Toobin knows all that, his characterization of the conference as “fevered” is inexcusable. (Watch the panels for yourself on YouTube.) Sure, there were intellectual fireworks, but that’s what every Federalist Society panel is about: robust intellectual debate. Panelists take reasoned legal positions and argue with the other panelists about legal substance. That’s something that Toobin can see at every Federalist Society event, and it’s really special, since open debate like that doesn’t happen much elsewhere.

Finally, Toobin gets to his primary target, former assistant attorney general in charge of DOJ’s Office of Legal Counsel Chuck Cooper. Cooper was one of three speakers at a lunchtime panel opining on the role of the coordinate branches of the government in checking the executive branch. Cooper gave his speech immediately between George Mason law professor Neomi Rao and Yale law professor William Eskridge (himself no conservative), both of whom gave provocative and illuminating speeches.

To hear Toobin tell the tale, Cooper gave a fiery speech endorsing impeachment. But that never happened. Watch the speech for yourself. Cooper was certainly the least academic of the panelists (he was, after all, the only non-academic), but, as you can see for yourself, he said nothing “radical.” Toobin completely ignores the tone and substance of Cooper’s speech, neither of which supports hysterical fear-mongering. As for impeachment talk, it’s hard to imagine an entire panel discussion devoted to Congress’s role in constraining the executive without discussing the legalities of the one direct mechanism that the Constitution actually gives to Congress for that purpose. Cooper carefully laid out the factual and legal analysis, none of which Toobin disputes on the merits, including ample quotes from liberal law professors who engaged with the impeachment issue during previous administrations.

But Cooper actually argued against impeachment, calling impeachment a “drastic” measure, and instead urging a bicameral censure resolution that would have no legal effect. Radical? Hardly. (Toobin notes that Cooper told him he doesn’t support impeachment.) But instead of reporting on, or even sparring with, any of Cooper’s arguments he opted to take this cheap shot at Cooper and the Federalist Society:

Still, the impeachment talk presents yet another illustration of the conservative movement’s radicalization. Once, it was only Tea Party zealots (and birther lunatics) who talked about Obama’s illegitimacy. Now it’s the grownups in the Federalist Society.

Toobin’s piece isn’t legal journalism; it’s click-bait for left-wing bloggers and pundits. He invokes conspiracy theories while claiming to repudiate them, misrepresents both tone and substance of the conference, and even slips in a jab at Cooper’s personal life and his views on same-sex marriage. His piece is ultimately little more than a misleading and dishonest attempt to demonize Chuck Cooper and the Federalist Society as part of what he calls “the conservative movement’s radicalization.” Hopefully his readers will pay more attention to the facts and arguments than he did.

This Day in Liberal Judicial Activism—May 15



Text  



2008—The California supreme court, by a vote of 4 to 3, invents a right to same-sex marriage under the state constitution. Chief justice Ronald M. George’s majority opinion offers the usual false assurances that he’s not just making it up and imposing his own policy preferences. Even more brazenly, George tries to defend his usurpation of the “people’s will” by arguing that the “provisions of the California Constitution itself constitute the ultimate expression of the people’s will.” In a sense, yes—when those provisions are faithfully and properly interpreted and applied. But not when judicial activists like George abuse them.

Six months later, California’s citizens vote to override the court’s ruling by approving Proposition 8, a measure that amends the state constitution to protect traditional marriage (but that will itself later become the victim of egregious acts of judicial activism).

ADVERTISEMENT

No Naïve Deed Goes Unpunished



Text  



Just a note on Fourth Circuit judge Roger Gregory, who sat on the panel that heard argument yesterday in a case challenging Virginia’s marriage laws and who, according to various accounts, was manifestly hostile to those laws.

Gregory was recess-appointed to the Fourth Circuit by President Clinton on December 27, 2000. His recess appointment would have expired at the end of 2001. But in a conciliatory measure for which he never received any meaningful credit, President George W. Bush included Gregory in his first batch of appellate nominees in May 2001, and Gregory was promptly confirmed to a lifetime position. He has consistently been among the most liberal members of that court.

Bush’s nomination of Gregory was the first of many steps by which the Fourth Circuit lost its reputation as the most stalwart court in the country and flipped dramatically into the Left’s grasp. Of its 13 active judges other than Gregory, eight are Democratic appointees (including five who are Obama appointees).

This Day in Liberal Judicial Activism—May 14



Text  



1970—President Richard M. Nixon, in one of the misdeeds for which he most deserves infamy, appoints Harry A. Blackmun to the Supreme Court. Blackmun, a boyhood friend of Chief Justice Warren Burger, had served on the Eighth Circuit since 1959. Before that, he had been in-house counsel for the Mayo Clinic. His appreciation for the outstanding work done by the fine doctors at the Mayo Clinic is said to have led him to regret that he himself did not become a doctor. Those with a proper appreciation of Blackmun’s Supreme Court decisionmaking—including, but by no means limited to, his notorious opinion in Roe v. Wade (see This Day for January 22)—might fairly observe that the medical profession’s loss was the nation’s … loss. 

2009—Ramona Ripston, executive director of the ACLU Foundation of Southern California and (per its website) the individual “responsible for all phases of the organization’s programs, including litigation,” takes part in a confidential strategy meeting with counsel planning to file a federal lawsuit against Proposition 8. After counsel files the complaint in Perry v. Schwarzenegger, Ripston’s organization will file pre-trial and post-trial amicus briefs in support of plaintiffs, and Ripston will publicly “rejoice” over Judge Vaughn Walker’s August 2010 ruling against Proposition 8.

But when Ripston’s husband, arch-activist Stephen Reinhardt, is assigned to the Ninth Circuit panel charged with reviewing Walker’s ruling, Reinhardt somehow will decline to recuse himself from the case.

Marriage and the Race to the Supreme Court: What to Look for at the Fourth Circuit



Text  



Now that we know which horse took home the roses at the Kentucky Derby (California Chrome), it’s time to consider the odds on another race — this one a relay that began in May, 1970,when two male students at the University of Minnesota applied for (and were, predictably, denied) a marriage license: Which state marriage law challenge will be first past the post in the U.S. Supreme Court?

For advocates of same-sex (or “genderless”) marriage, the prize in this race is a Supreme Court majority opinion that invalidates all state laws that define marriage as the union of one man and one woman.  The U.S. Supreme Court refused to take that step in United States v. Windsor, but many interpret it as hinting strongly that both Congress and the states must grant legal recognition to same-sex marriages, and that that anyone who refuses to do likewise is a bigot.  Windsor was thus the opening shot in what most legal commentators agree will be the last two legs of the race.

Over 60 challenges to state marriage laws have been filed in state and federal courts since Windsor was decided in June, 2013. Taking their cue from Justice Kennedy’s opinion in that case, the lower courts have uniformly held that laws defining marriage as a union of one man and one woman are unconstitutional.  The action (and drama) now shifts to the federal circuit courts.  An appeal from one or more of the cases currently pending will inevitably put the marriage question front-and-center on the U.S. Supreme Court’s docket in the 2014-2015 Term.  Which case will it pick?

To date, the Tenth Circuit has heard oral arguments in challenges to Utah’s and Oklahoma’s marriage amendments, but has yet to issue an opinion.  While we wait for those opinions, all eyes now turn to the Richmond-based Fourth Circuit, which will hear oral arguments today in Bostic v. Rainey, a challenge to Virginia’s marriage laws.  

Bostic is a “case-to-watch” for several reasons.

Virginia’s marriage laws defining marriage as the union of one man and one woman have been on the books since 1632.

The nature and scope of the fundamental right to marry is at issue.  While Loving v. Virginia and multiple other Supreme Court decisions have affirmed the fundamental right to marry, it has always been assumed that the relationship involved would be male-female.  Advocates of same-sex marriage are attempting to expand the scope of this fundamental right to marry to include same-sex couples (“non-gendered” relationships) relying on this precedent, so it will be interesting to see how judges address this issue.

In the Tenth Circuit, the litigants knew who the panel members would be prior to the day of argument.  In Bostic, the litigants will not learn the members of the Fourth Circuit panel until the morning of oral arguments.  

Good lawyers know that the make-up of the court will play a big role in the oral arguments and in the majority’s reasoning once the case is decided.

So, what do we know about the judges on the Fourth Circuit? Sixteen judges sit on the Fourth Circuit: Six were appointed by President Obama, four by President Clinton, one by President Reagan, and five by Presidents George H.W. Bush and George W. Bush.

Though oral arguments are rarely the occasion for placing bets, they do provide excellent scouting opportunities.  A judge’s questions provide valuable insights on his or her approach to the issues in the case, so pay particular attention to which judges are on the panel, to the questions they ask, and to their reactions to the advocates’ answers.  

We will want to know, in particular, whether they accept the lower court’s premise that ”love and commitment to one another” is the only constitutionally-acceptable definition of a marriage.  We will also want to know whether the panel judges appear to agree that Virginia’s understanding of marriage as a relationship between one man and one woman is, like race discrimination, a ”law . . . rooted in unlawful prejudice.”

For answers to these questions and more, stay tuned. The audio recording of the oral argument will be available on the Fourth Circuit’s website on Thursday, May 15.

— Robert A. Destro is professor of law and founding director of the Interdisciplinary Program in Law & Religion at The Catholic University of America’s Columbus School of Law in Washington, D.C.

 

This Day in Liberal Judicial Activism—May 13



Text  



1993—In dissent in University of Miami v. Echarte, Florida chief justice Rosemary Barkett flouts U.S. Supreme Court precedent as she opines that a statutory cap on non-economic damages in medical malpractice cases violates the Equal Protection Clause of the federal Constitution. Nominated a few months later by President Clinton to the Eleventh Circuit, Barkett concedes at her confirmation hearing that she “should not have done that.” But, hey, activism happens—when, that is, reckless judges like Barkett are involved.

To make matters even worse: Barkett’s dissent adopts the position taken in an amicus brief submitted in the case by the Academy of Florida Trial Lawyers. While the case was pending and while Barkett was facing a retention election, this same group created an annual award named after her, the Rosemary Barkett Award. In November 1992, one week after her successful retention election, Barkett presented the first annual Rosemary Barkett Award at the group’s annual convention. So much for the fact and appearance of impartiality.  

David J. Barron, Part 5: ‘Big Waiver’



Text  



So far in my series about David J. Barron (Part 1, Part 2, Part 3, and Part 4), President Obama’s pick for the First Circuit Court of Appeals, I have emphasized that Barron’s judicial philosophy would incorporate an agenda for using constitutional law to accomplish political objectives which he calls “progressive constitutionalism.” This agenda includes the deliberate inversion of the Constitution’s federal scheme.

This post addresses another serious defect in Barron’s view of the Constitution: his belief that Congress can simply allow the Executive Branch the broad ability to “waive” inconvenient laws. To his credit, Barron doesn’t endorse President Obama’s apparent view that the president can refuse to enforce duly enacted laws on his own constitutional authority. Instead, Barron proposes that Congress do something almost as bad: authorize the President to refuse to enforce duly enacted laws. As Barron describes, this would take the following form: “Congress passes a statute telling an agency to accomplish, among other things, X, and Congress also empowers the agency to waive part or all of X.”

He calls that “Big Waiver”. The purpose of “Big Waiver” is, in Barron’s view, to allow administrative agencies to “displace a regulatory baseline that Congress itself has established.” In other words, Barron wants Congress to let agencies rewrite congressionally enacted policies.

This sort of waiver, especially the broad kind that Barron favors, flies in the face of the non-delegation doctrine, a separation-of-powers rule requiring that laws announce an “intelligible principle.” As Justice Scalia explained the non-delegation doctrine in Whitman v. American Trucking Ass’ns, the question is whether a statute has delegated legislative power to the agency, which would be forbidden since the Constitution vests legislative power solely in Congress. Congress can avoid a wholesale delegation of its legislative power by setting out an “intelligible principle” for the Executive to follow rather than giving an agency free rein to add (or, here, remove) content to congressionally enacted laws.

Affirming Big Waiver’s constitutionality by weakening the non-delegation doctrine would, in Barron’s view, offer benefits that he sees in several of the Obama Administration’s key policy priorities. For instance, the Administration aggressively used provisions of the No Child Left Behind legislation to grant waivers to 33 states and Washington, D.C., allowing these states to receive federal funds but ignore congressional policy. Barron also lauds the Affordable Care Act’s waiver provisions,which allow states to be exempted from the ACA’s elements by proposing their own health-care schemes, and the Secretary of Health and Human Services’ move to waive work requirements as a condition of receiving welfare funds. (On the latter point, Barron delicately describes HHS’s statutory interpretation as “by no means self-evident.”)

Barron mentions several more examples, but the sticking point in all of these “Big Waiver” provisions is this: granting the waivers lies entirely within the discretion of the relevant department. The statutes authorizing waivers amount to vast delegations of power to the executive branch, not only to act, but not to act, and to specify the conditions under which waiver will be granted. The power to declare the law not to be the law is effectively a new form of delegation.

And Barron is all for it. He argues that Big Waiver makes the government better able to do a variety of things, including “establish positive rights through direct welfare provision.” He considers it an advantage to allow the federal government to treat parties differently by allowing for “nonuniform, easily revised problem-solving efforts.” Most of all, Barron thinks it is the perfect tool for avoiding “legislative gridlock” (which the Framers would have called “checks” and “balances”). He even endorses the outrageous idea that Congress should vote for legislation in bad faith:

Legislators of the same party as the President can sign on to seemingly detailed and restrictive legislation that constrains him, knowing that the President’s interests will be protected (if at a high cost) through the safety valve that waiver provisions afford. And legislators of the opposite party can stomach the delegation of authority to the executive precisely because they can spell out in the statute their own preferred regulatory approach, thereby saddling the President with the decision to displace it. In this way, legislators can claim credit for having solved a problem, while either downplaying the significance of the fact that the supposed “solution” is actually far from stable or highlighting to their favored constituents in relatively discrete tones the instability of those features of the framework that cause concern to those same constituents.

In essence, Barron is cynically proposing that members of Congress vote for bad policy because there’s an escape hatch somewhere, to be exercised someday. Moreover, he proposes that this sort of power-driven log-rolling could convince the executive branch to agree to legislation it has no intention of executing: “Further, the executive branch may be comfortable accepting legislative terms that might otherwise be unacceptable precisely because it also receives the power to waive them.” The key, from Barron’s perspective, is to unleash the executive branch so it can ignore longstanding statutes. As he writes, “An effective, engaged, and democratically responsive administrative state, on this view, cannot be one that is hemmed in by federal legislative baselines enacted decades ago.”

Evaluating Big Waiver within the context of modern non-delegation doctrine, Barron says that judges “should defer to Congress’s judgment as to when the technique is ‘necessary and proper’ in all but very extreme cases,” says that the question of whether an agency has waiver power should be decided “without deference to the agency’s judgment,” but then also says that the precise range of the agency’s waiver power and the conditions to be placed on it should receive “substantial deference.” There’s more than a little wiggle room in these definitions, and one cannot help but suspect that this is designed to give latitude to “progressive constitutionalists” who might judicially review the waivers.

There’s no question that Congress should repeal many of the laws it has passed. But the central question that ought to concern us with Barron’s endorsement of Big Waiver is not whether Congress is, as Barron says, “stuck with a prior legislative judgment it no longer believes is wise.” That is an easy question, at least under the Constitution: Congress can repeal the law. But Barron would have Congress totally abdicate its Constitutional role in the amending and repealing of laws and further asks federal judges to concur in that abdication. In sum, it seems clear that Barron fundamentally misunderstands the role that democratic accountability has to play in this republican democracy.

David J. Barron, Part 4: An Enemy of Federalism and the Private Sphere



Text  



In Part 4 of my series about First Circuit nominee David J. Barron (Part 1, Part 2, & Part 3), I will discuss two implications of Barron’s radical left-wing judicial philosophy. (For those who haven’t yet read my previous posts, Barron’s nomination is currently held up because an unlikely left-right coalition, now including the New York Times, demanded the release of his OLC opinion blessing the use of drone strikes against American terrorists overseas.) As I previously noted, Barron’s chief concern with constitutional law seems to be not the faithful exposition of existing laws, such as the Constitution and federal statutes, but the creation of a “progressive constitutionalism” that will use the federal courts to advance “progressive” political goals.

This post focuses on two areas in which this “progressive constitutionalism” might take shape, namely, federalism and the public and private spheres. As we will see, Barron treats federalism as if it were nothing more than a political tool, and treats the existence of a private sphere as something that only exists at sufferance of the government.

1. Federalism

As you know, federalism is the obvious fact that the Constitution divides powers between the states and the national government. Barron’s vision of federalism turns the constitutional balance on its head in an effort to achieve progressive policy goals by giving states more authority to enact stringent regulations of commerce and by giving the federal government more power in the social sphere, presumably to liberalize abortion and marriage laws.

Americans have always debated what the proper allocation of powers should be, but it is unquestionable that under the Constitution, the national government’s powers are (as James Madison put it in Federalist No. 45) “few and defined” and that the state governments’ powers are “numerous and indefinite.” The Tenth Amendment makes these assumptions explicit, stating “The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the states, are reserved to the states respectively, or to the people.” (emphasis added).

But in an essay published in William Lasser’s Perspectives on American Politics, Barron discounts the notion that federalism might constrain the federal government’s power in ways that progressives don’t like:

The notion that there might be some federalism-based limits on national power, after all, is not senseless. But there is precious little in the Constitution’s text or the history of its adoption that compels the particular conservative allocation of national and local powers favored by the Rehnquist Court.

Barron’s argument is intended to undermine the idea that the Constitution’s text and structure require the Rehnquist Court’s belated rediscovery of federalism-based limits on national power, thus elevating his own non-textual, “progressive” ideas about the Constitution to the same level. As he explicitly urges progressives in an article published in the Fordham Law Review, “[A]ny Justice who has anything like a substantive constitutional vision should also be expected to have some such conception of the proper vertical allocation of powers and one that will promote rather than undermine that vision.” By “substantive constitutional vision,” Barron is referring to the “progressive constitutionalism” that I discussed in Part 2.

But it is amazing that Barron can only find “precious little” certainty about the Constitution’s division of powers.  The text is clear enough; the enumerated federal powers and the reservation of powers to the states and citizens should make the constitutional vision clear. And the history goes into even greater depth. 

For example, and contrary to what Barron suggests, federal pre-emption of state and local economic regulations is not some sort of arbitrary “conservative” move by the courts. For one thing, the Supremacy Clause ensures that laws passed under Congress’s enumerated powers cannot be sabotaged by any individual state. This was one problem with the Articles of Confederation that the Constitution would solve. As Alexander Hamilton pointed out in Federalist No. 22:

The interfering and unneighborly regulations of some States, contrary to the true spirit of the Union, have, in different instances, given just cause of umbrage and complaint to others, and it is to be feared that examples of this nature, if not restrained by a national control, would be multiplied and extended till they became not less serious sources of animosity and discord than injurious impediments to the intercourse between the different parts of the Confederacy [referring to the Articles of Confederation]. 

There are other examples. Hamilton emphasized in Federalist No. 11 that vesting interstate commercial regulation within the exclusive power of the federal government would benefit the whole nation by encouraging foreign trade.

I’m no fan of the Supreme Court’s Commerce Clause jurisprudence as a whole, but there’s no denying that in the early days of the Republic, Hamilton won this point by securing ratification of the Constitution with both the Commerce and Necessary and Proper Clauses. There is no clause giving Congress a power of “social regulation,” so Barron’s proposal to expand federal power in that sphere seems to rest completely on wishful thinking.

If Barron’s objection seems odd to you, remember that Barron’s entire enterprise is designed to encourage liberals to be less bashful about using constitutional law as a tool of their politics. For him to defeat the claims of originalism, Barron has to pretend that originalist constitutional analysis is nothing more than a “conservative” version of the sort of legal agenda he is creating for progressives, even though he often (in this essay and in other works) expresses consternation that originalist legal analysis doesn’t always lead to “conservative” results. That’s why later in his essay, Barron can cast a vision of economic and social powers that reverses the allocation actually stated in the text of the Constitution and still say, without evident embarrassment, that his vision “has a constitutional pedigree that is at least as legitimate as the conservative one it would displace.”

While Barron doesn’t make clear what he means by “constitutional pedigree” (perhaps Progressive Era or Warren Court judicial precedent?), his vision is so atextual and ahistorical that it can only be attributed to his “progressive” political views.  Even the progressive results he seeks would not be achieved in a particularly principled manner.  His arguments seem not to rest on why a different allocation of powers would be good as a general matter, but rather on which allocation would lead to his favored results in today’s political climate.  While he may currently find the federal government’s regulation of commerce too lax and states’ regulation of social matters too strict, there is nothing preventing him from reversing his vision as the political winds change.

When a man has built his career around telling progressives how to use constitutional law to accomplish their policy goals ascends the federal bench, we should not expect him to stop just because he puts on a robe.

2. Public and Private Spheres

In his zeal to contradict everything “conservative” about the Supreme Court’s jurisprudence, Barron has made clear that he doesn’t believe that there is any realm of life that is truly “private” and considers it something of an oddity that the Supreme Court would recognize the existence of a “free world” where government is absent. His essay entitled “Privatizing the Constitution: State Action and Beyond” criticizes theoretical boundaries on the modern “state action” doctrine as articulated by the late Justice Rehnquist, which generally says that the Constitution only limits the conduct of the government, not that of private actors.

Barron’s essay is especially critical of Rehnquist’s idea that the state is absent from certain sorts of transactions and situations. Barron dismissively describes Rehnquist’s view as articulating a world in which there is “either coercion or freedom.” In Barron’s view, the state is involved simply by noninvolvement; acts and omissions are equally representative of policy choices by the state. In this scheme, private action takes place “at the state’s sufferance.” To Barron, the idea that child abuse from a parent is not a Due Process Clause violation (as Rehnquist wrote in the heartbreaking case of DeShaney v. Winnebago County) was an example of “privatizing.” He also criticizes Rehnquist’s majority opinion in United States v. Morrison, which showed that the federal government did not have power under the Commerce Clause or the Fourteenth Amendment to create a federal civil rights claim for personal gender-based violence.

As before, Barron’s thoroughgoing commitment to judging as concealed policymaking is on full display. Barron asks why Rehnquist thinks the private/public distinction is “attractive,” as if deciding cases is some sort of beauty contest. Barron also accuses Rehnquist of “avert[ing] his eyes” from state involvement in DeShaney. Barron is so enmeshed in the law-as-policymaking paradigm that he considers it noteworthy and significant that Rehnquist could consider “the ‘free world’ as a mandatory fact the government must respect, rather than an option government may choose to recognize.”

Is it really possible that the President’s nominee believes that “free world” exists only at the sufferance of the government? Chilling.

This Day in Liberal Judicial Activism—May 12



Text  



2005—Federal district judge Joseph F. Bataillon rules that the Nebraska constitutional provision defining marriage as “between a man and a woman” violates First Amendment associational rights, the Equal Protection Clause, and the Bill of Attainder Clause. One year later, a unanimous Eighth Circuit panel reverses all of these rulings.

This Day in Liberal Judicial Activism—May 11



Text  



2014—Happy Mother’s Day! No thanks to Ruth Bader Ginsburg, who in 1974 co-authored a report proposing that Congress abolish Mother’s Day and Father’s Day and replace them with an androgynous Parents’ Day. Observing Parents’ Day would, she explained, be “more consistent with a policy of minimizing traditional sex-based differences in parental roles.”

In that same report, the oh-so-“moderate” Ginsburg stated her strong sympathy for the proposition that there is a constitutional right to prostitution and a constitutional right to bigamy; criticized the Boy Scouts and the Girl Scouts for perpetuating stereotyped sex roles; and urged that prisons be co-ed rather than single sex. (See here for relevant excerpts from the report.)

This Day in Liberal Judicial Activism—May 10



Text  



2006—Mississippi attorney Michael B. Wallace, nominated to the Fifth Circuit by President Bush, is victimized by the ABA. In a scandalous process marked by bias, a glaring conflict of interest, incompetence (see here and here), a stacked committee, violation of its own procedures, cheap gamesmanship, and ultimately, flat-out perjury, the ABA committee rates Wallace “not qualified.”  After Democrats regain control of the Senate in 2007, Wallace’s nomination is not resubmitted.

2011—In what Chief Judge Alex Kozinski’s dissent labels an “Article III putsch,” Ninth Circuit rebel Stephen Reinhardt issues a 77-page majority opinion (in Veterans for Common Sense v. Shinseki) that would place the Department of Veterans Affairs’ mental-health-treatment and disability-compensation programs under the direct supervision of a federal district judge. One year later, an en banc panel of the Ninth Circuit will reverse Reinhardt by a 10-1 vote, with even all five Clinton appointees on the panel voting against Reinhardt.

Town of Greece Decision Brings Needed Common Sense to Establishment Clause . . . and to New York City



Text  



The U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in the Town of Greece v. Galloway prayer case brings a common-sense balance to the understanding of the Establishment Clause, an area of law fraught with fevered and excessive applications.

This week, Alliance Defending Freedom, which litigated the Town of Greece case, asked the en banc U.S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit to use that decision to reverse a recent 2–1 panel decision in another important case that ADF is litigating. That decision upheld New York City’s exclusion of religious worship services from a policy allowing local groups to rent vacant public schools for any activity “pertaining to the welfare of the community.”

ADF represents a small evangelical church, Bronx Household of Faith, which has been challenging this policy that has kept the congregation’s worship services out of nearby schools since 1995.  In early April, the Second Circuit ruled that the New York City Department of Education’s concern about a possible violation of the Establishment Clause allows it to violate the First Amendment rights of religious groups by excluding their worship services. The Town of Greece decision rejects that overly Establishment Clause-centric view of religious liberty and freedom of speech.

ADF submitted a letter Tuesday to the Second Circuit pointing out three ways the Town of Greece decision rejects the panel’s extreme view of the Establishment Clause in its Bronx Household of Faith decision.  The Supreme Court said that, “so long as the town maintains a policy of nondiscrimination” among religions, it does not violate the Establishment Clause. Certainly, New York City does not violate the Establishment Clause when it opens the doors of its empty school buildings to community groups to use on a first-come, first-served basis. This is government accommodation of religion, which is not government endorsement of religion.

Second, the Supreme Court said that “the Establishment Clause must be interpreted by reference to historical practices and understandings” and then referred to the fact that the House of Representatives created an office of the chaplain to lead prayers for that body within days of approving the text of the Establishment Clause. Similarly, history informs the Bronx Household of Faith situation. Congress allowed churches to conduct worship services in the U.S. Capitol for about 70 years, from about 1800 until after the Civil War. While president, Thomas Jefferson attended weekly worship services at the House of Representatives.

In Town of Greece, the Supreme Court wrote that the Establishment Clause prohibits the government from excessively entangling itself with religion when it “seek[s] to define permissible categories of religious speech” by dissecting prayers in order to determine which are too “sectarian” and which are acceptable. Similarly in Bronx Household of Faith, New York City school district officials were deciding whether a religious meeting was a forbidden “worship service” or an acceptable religious meeting. Such determinations are not the business of the government.

Right now, churches and other religious congregations are still meeting in the schools because the Second Circuit has not yet allowed the panel decision to go into effect, which means the lower-court order finding the policy unconstitutional remains in effect for now. If the Second Circuit votes to reject our petition for re-hearing, ADF will likely appeal the case to the U.S. Supreme Court.

The Supreme Court’s decision in Town of Greece brings a more balanced approach to the Establishment Clause doctrine. It refutes the extreme notion pushed by separationist groups that, in essence, the Establishment Clause requires the government to go on a “search and destroy” mission to obliterate religious expression from public life, no matter what the context, and no matter whether the religious expression is state-sponsored or initiated by private speakers.

Town of Greece shows that New York City is wrong to think that Establishment Clause “concerns” require this policy banning worship services. The government does not show “neutrality” towards religion by treating religious groups and their expression worse than everyone else.

 Jordan Lorence is senior counsel with Alliance Defending Freedom, which represents Bronx Household of Faith in its lawsuit at the U.S. Court of Appeals for the 2nd Circuit. ADF also represented the town of Greece in its case at the U.S. Supreme Court.

David J. Barron, Part 3: In Which I Praise Barron



Text  



In my last two posts about Professor David J. Barron (Part 1 and Part 2), I made clear that Barron’s confirmation to the U.S. Court of Appeals for the First Circuit should be opposed in large part because of his views about the Constitution, the law, and the purpose of judges.

In this post, however, I want to point out one incident that actually weighs in favor of Barron’s personal integrity, if not his judicial philosophy. As you may know, Barron was acting head of the Department of Justice’s Office of Legal Counsel (OLC) from 2009–10. In that capacity, he was responsible for advising the president about the meaning of the Constitution and federal law. Historically, OLC has been responsible for interpreting the law in a nonpolitical way that maintains continuity between administrations.

In 2009, according to a Washington Post op-ed by my Bench Memos colleague Ed Whelan, Barron signed an OLC opinion instructing Attorney General Eric Holder that a pending bill to give the District of Columbia a voting right in the House of Representatives was unconstitutional. As Whelan notes, that view has been the opinion of every Department of Justice as far back as 1963, regardless of the party holding the presidency.

Attorney General Holder and President Obama, however, supported the bill for political reasons. Attorney General Holder therefore overrode OLC’s opinion. Instead of pointing out an error in Barron’s OLC opinion or issuing his own contradictory analysis, Holder asked Acting Solicitor General Neal Katyal whether the D.C. voting bill could be defended in court, which is a far less strict inquiry. Holder didn’t ask whether the bill was actually constitutional, just whether it could be defended. (Hypocrisy alert: Holder had no such interest in defending the Defense of Marriage Act, a federal statute passed by lopsided bipartisan majorities in Congress and signed into law by a Democrat.) Holder then declared the D.C. voting bill constitutional.

Without knowing the details of Barron’s opinion, we can’t really know whether he was simply representing his client, DOJ, or whether the DOJ opinion was actually his personal view. It’s certainly unusual, though, for such a politically motivated lawyer to stand up to President Obama on an issue as important to Democrats as D.C. voting rights. He must have known that the memo would subject him to frivolous accusations that he endorsed the disenfranchisement of voters. And for that he should be congratulated. 

A Reply to Tepp -- There Was Nothing “Conservative” about Eldred Decision



Text  



I will leave the debate about what constitutes “conservative” copyright reform to others, as that’s not my area of expertise. There is one claim in Stephen Tepp’s recent article, “Assailing Copyright Isn’t Conservative,” however, that merits a response.

In his article, Tepp claims that the Supreme Court’s Eldred v. Ashcroft is a “conservative” decision because in this case “the conservative justices overwhelmingly sided with private property.”  Lest anyone be confused, what happened in this case is that the Court agreed to recognize a congressional grant of private property, and in the process made a mockery of the constitutional text.  

Contrary to Justice Ginsburg’s suggestion in Eldred, the copyright clause of the Constitution does not give Congress an unfettered right to grant copyrights or other forms of intellectual property.  Rather, the clause only grants Congress the power “to promote the progress of science and the useful arts.”  The power to grant copyrights — specifically the power to “secur[e] for limited time to authors and inventors the exclusive right to their respective writings and discoveries” — only exists insofar as it serves the constitutionally enumerated end, and the retrospective extension of copyrights in pre-existing works does not serve that end.  Extending the copyright term for a work that has already been created or, worse, restoring copyright to items that have already entered the public domain, does not “promote progress” as it does nothing to encourage the creation of new works — the sole end Congress may use its copyright power to pursue.  It’s true that the conservative justices joined Justice Ginsburg’s opinion, but that’s not because her opinion embraced conservative principle or properly applied the clear constitutional text.  If one wants to read a constitutional conservative take on the constitutional question, I ‘d ignore what the Supreme Court said in Eldred and instead look at Judge Sentelle’s dissent below in the U.S. Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit.  

David J. Barron, Part 2: ‘Progressive Constitutionalism’



Text  



This is the second in my series of posts about the judicial philosophy of David J. Barron, President Obama’s judicial nominee to the First Circuit Court of Appeals. As I noted in Part 1, Barron has left us ample information about his judicial philosophy through his academic publications. If confirmed, Barron would seek to use the federal judiciary as a weapon in pursuit of what he calls “progressive constitutionalism.”

In a 2006 piece for the liberal Harvard Law and Policy Review, Barron laid out his vision of “progressive constitutionalism” in an article entitled “What’s Wrong With Conservative Constitutionalism? Two Styles of Progressive Constitutional Critique and the Choice They Present.” Though it’s now long-gone from the HLPR website, you can still read it yourself here. Progressive constitutionalism, so far as I can make out, appears to be a less modest version of what earlier generations of academics called “living constitutionalism.” Although the “progressive” variant uses similar language to living constitutionalism, describing the Constitution as “a dynamic document” and caricaturing originalism as a “frozen” Constitution, it is more strident, less deferential to democratic processes, and more explicit about its willingness to use the Constitution instrumentally.

The article contrasts two strains of left-wing academic thinking about the constitution. One of these strains, according to Barron, focuses on using democratic mechanisms to enact desirable laws and take executive action as a means of “giving life” to the Constitution. In Barron’s view, this strain is “anti-Court” because it seeks to use Congress and the Presidency to advance left-wing policy positions while urging the courts to “get out of the way.” The other strain, which Barron clearly favors, seeks to “take the substantive claims of conservative constitutionalism seriously and to challenge them in ways that will not thereby justify broad judicial deference to political actors.” In other words, Barron wants judges to counter what he describes as “conservative constitutionalism” and “conservative judicial activism” with a vision of the Constitution that does not require courts to defer to democratically-selected policymakers.

One of the ways that courts can do this, Barron suggests, is by pre-empting public opinion. For instance, he lauds the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court:

Such protections [same-sex civil unions and adoption rights], rooted in state constitutional interpretation, have generally held up against political efforts to overturn them, but there is little doubt that state legislatures would not have responded as quickly without judicial intervention. It was courts acting in advance of political will that made the difference.  [emphasis added]

In case there were any doubt that Barron thinks courts should have primacy, he hails state supreme courts (such as New Jersey’s) for overriding state legislatures:

State supreme courts, not state legislatures, have also led the revolution in school financing equality, though judicial actions have catalyzed political responses. Thus, the progressive Anti-Court critique that targets so vigorously the federal Supreme Court’s activism only feeds the conservative mantra that courts in general are overstepping their bounds in issuing rights-protecting decisions. Yet progressive constitutionalists enamored of the Anti-Court rhetoric rarely take account of its potential downstream effects on state-court interpretation and legitimacy.

The last sentence of that quote is chilling: Barron is worried that by asking federal courts to behave in a “conservative” way, state courts might become bashful about “leading the revolution” in progressive policy. In Barron’s vision, judges rule and must be free from any influences that might sway them from their heady task.

Barron also makes clear that the desired “progressive constitutionalism” is not derived from legal texts such as the Constitution, its amendments, or the laws created by Congress. No, this “progressive constitutionalism” is something to be engineered for political ends. He writes:

I want to emphasize, once again, that I do not mean to suggest that the reason the Anti-Court progressive constitutionalists — including Post and Siegel in this piece — wish to shift the forum from courts to legislatures or popular decision making is simply in order to generate more progressive outcomes. Sometimes, of course, this seems to be the point the Anti-Courtists wish to make. But that is not always clear. They may wish only (or primarily) to generate popular constitutional control. If that is the case, however, then it becomes harder to see their position as being one that sounds in progressive constitutionalism, unless progressive constitutionalism is to be equated with a defense of popular constitutionalism independent of the substantive outcomes it would generate. [emphasis added]

In other words, what makes a “progressive constitutionalism” important is that it achieve progressive “outcomes.” One might consider Barron’s ideal federal judge to be a life-tenured philosopher-king, handing down “substantive outcomes” from Mount Olympus.

Barron also thinks that a constitutional theory should be chosen based on what is popular, not whether it is true. He writes:

Superficially, of course, it may seem that the Anti-Court style of critique is deadly accurate, if only because the rhetoric that it relies upon in critiquing contemporary conservative constitutionalism seems to have real public appeal, something that cannot be said for some other progressive constitutional rhetorical traditions. But I am doubtful that this Anti-Court rhetoric will remain powerful over time. There is a sense, at present, that turnabout is fair play.

Read that again: the acceptability of the opposing view is based on whether it “will remain powerful over time,” not whether it is “accurate.” Again, chilling.

If Barron’s view of the courts seems radical to you, you’re not alone. Two of the left-wing academics discussed in Barron’s article, Robert Post and Reva Siegel, called Barron out for being a judicial supremacist:

These matters need to be carefully and contextually studied. Insisting on separating law from politics in order to preserve the purity of the law’s substantive commitments will do no good if it causes us to ignore the sources of the law’s actual legitimacy. Only in legal process textbooks is law about contentious matters wholly independent of politics. This is not simply a regrettable reality; it is a democratic good. Democracies require the rule of law — as well the kind of dialogue among courts, the political branches, and the voting public that makes the rule of law responsive to the community. No progressive would want to live in a state where the authority of “We the People” refers only to the professional opinion of judges.

Barron responded that Post and Siegel failed to see that the biggest danger to the progressive agenda is not posed by judicial supremacy, but rather by popular opinion.

These excerpts make clear that Barron favors using the federal courts as a platform to advance a “progressive constitutionalism” that will achieve the desired policy results. His view doesn’t really deserve to be called “constitutionalism” at all, since it is derived from philosophical premises and political commitments that are entirely alien to the Constitution. In this respect, Barron’s judicial philosophy is not only radical, but inconsistent with the entire American legal tradition.

David J. Barron: Part 1

This Day in Liberal Judicial Activism—May 8



Text  



2006—When left-wing activist and divorce specialist Marna Tucker is somehow selected as the D.C. Circuit member of the ABA committee that rates federal judicial nominees, Senate Democrats engineer the occasion for Tucker to conduct a (supposedly) supplemental review of White House lawyer Brett M. Kavanaugh, who had previously received an overall “well qualified” rating. Tucker instead launches a scorched-earth investigation that produces a jumble of biased and incoherent allegations, and the ABA committee reduces Kavanaugh’s overall rating to “qualified.”

Amidst the ensuing Democratic smears, Kavanaugh ends up being confirmed to the D.C. Circuit by a vote of 57-36. (See here for a fuller account.)   

David J. Barron, Part 1: Unabashedly Radical



Text  



With reelection and the exercise of the nuclear option behind him, President Obama has now nominated David J. Barron, to the U.S. Court of Appeals for the First Circuit.

This is the first of what will be several posts describing David J. Barron’s views of the law, the Constitution, and what Barron would be like as a federal judge. For a judicial nominee, Barron’s record is unusually rich, revealing his views of the law, the Constitution, and his judicial philosophy.

Barron was a judicial clerk for Judge Stephen R. Reinhardt, one of the most liberal judges on the uber-liberal Ninth Circuit, and for Justice John Paul Stevens. He worked as an Attorney-Advisor in the Department of Justice’s Office of Legal Counsel (OLC) during the Clinton years and after that obtained a faculty position at Harvard Law School, where he is now a tenured professor. In 2009, after President Obama was elected, Barron rejoined OLC as Acting Assistant Attorney General and left in 2010.

Barron’s nomination is especially notable because of the strange-bedfellows coalition opposing it, at least for now. Code Pink, Republican Senator Rand Paul, the ACLU, and Democratic Senators Ron Wyden and Mark Udall have joined together to prevent a confirmation vote. Democratic Senators Mark Begich and Mary Landrieu are “unsure” whether they will vote for Mr. Barron’s nomination. The bipartisan opposition is refusing to proceed until they receive memos drafted or approved by Barron during his time at OLC that relate to OLC’s approval of an overseas drone strike against American citizen and terrorist Anwar al-Awlaki. OLC has refused to release the full memos thus far, preventing resolution of the conflict. (Ironically, Barron signed off on a list of proposed guidelines demanding the “timely” release of OLC memos back when George W. Bush was president.)

But there’s much more worrying information about Mr. Barron than his mere partisan inconsistency. In short, Barron is a judicial supremacist who wants to use the federal judiciary as a weapon to advance his hard-left political vision. Stay tuned.

Pages

Sign up for free NRO e-mails today:

Subscribe to National Review