Justice Alito’s Call to Action

Supreme Court justice Samuel Alito poses during a group photo of the Justices at the Supreme Court in Washington, D.C., April 23, 2021. (Erin Schaff/Reuters)

In remarks this week, the Supreme Court justice and Dobbs author made clear that others must participate in the conversation about originalism.

Sign in here to read more.

In remarks this week, the Supreme Court justice and Dobbs author made clear that others must participate in the conversation about originalism.

S upreme Court Justice Samuel Alito has been relatively quiet since June 24. That day marked the release of the majority opinion he authored in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization, which reversed the abortion regime imposed by Roe v. Wade and mostly upheld by Planned Parenthood v. Casey. But yesterday, as the inaugural guest speaker of the Catholic University of America Columbus School of Law’s new Project on Constitutional Originalism and the Catholic Intellectual Tradition (of whose advisory council he is an honorary chairman), Alito broke his silence somewhat. In careful remarks that neither mentioned his most consequential judicial act nor officially weighed in on some of the questions currently being debated within constitutional jurisprudence, Alito nonetheless set a challenge for those working and thinking in this sphere.

Alito was modest in his apparent aims, describing the goal of his remarks as simply to “set the stage for the work that will follow” for “the players at the main event” of the program he was helping to begin. He noted the live debate over whether “originalism is compatible with the Catholic intellectual tradition,” citing critics of originalism from this perspective while stressing that their critique “has not gone unanswered.” One such answer, Alito noted, has come from J. Joel Alicea, co-director of the program and a former Alito clerk. But rather than focus on this debate, Alito attempted to provide a précis of some of the lingering questions about originalism, as well as some guideposts for how future thought in this area might proceed fruitfully.

Constitutional originalism has been a contested notion. Alito defined it as the “theory that the Constitution should be interpreted according to its original public meaning.” But he admitted that this definition leaves many questions about interpretation unanswered. Indeed, he argued that originalism was initially “under-theorized.” But since the founding of constitutional originalism in the 1970s as a reaction to Supreme Court excesses of that time, originalists have attempted to resolve some of these questions.

Now, originalism has so penetrated the study of the Constitution that, Alito argued, “all should be grateful even if they loathe the doctrine,” as, if nothing else, it helped some of its most fervent critics gain employment. Alito even agreed with his Supreme Court colleague Elena Kagan’s contention that “we are all originalists now,” albeit with serious qualifications.

One is that, even if the Constitution and its amendments are the guide for interpretation, “there is a lot of disagreement over how that meaning should be found.” Alito cited the Supreme Court’s decision in Obergefell v. Hodges, joined by Kagan, which legalized same-sex marriage, as one such example. Others have attempted to justify that right on originalist grounds based on the “original public meaning” of the 14th Amendment. But Scalia, Alito, and Thomas, dissenting in Obergefell, disputed the majority’s conclusion that the 14th Amendment’s due-process clause protected a liberty that could have feasibly encompassed same-sex marriage. Their dissent argued that the due-process clause protected only those rights that are “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition,” which indisputably did not include the right to same-sex marriage. Thus, because of this internal debate among putative originalists about what originalism actually means, “the relationship between each of these subcultures” of originalism with the Catholic intellectual tradition might differ.

What also may be different, Alito argued, is the nature of a judge’s role in distinct circumstances. Recalling a time when Justice Scalia criticized Thomas Aquinas in the presence of Dominicans (the order to which Aquinas belonged) for once having written that a judge could make decisions on the basis of “equity,” Alito argued that the role of a judge may have been different in settings with which Aquinas was familiar. Likewise, Alito’s reply to a famous challenge by Judge Richard Posner, accusing originalists who liked classical music that wasn’t played by its original design of an inconsistency for preferring to interpret the Constitution in that manner, was that we should look to the “terms of employment” for a judge to clarify the nature of the role.

In some instances, history can also be a guide; in others, however, its guidance is a bit more uncertain. Indeed, the justice asked us to consider how to think about such questions when “no historical analogue comes to mind” for a given situation. To demonstrate, Alito cited cases in which technology beyond the conception of the Founding was at issue. One case, Brown v. Entertainment Merchants Association, concerned a state ban on the sale of violent video games to minors. Another case, U.S. v. Jones, concerned the use by law enforcement of a GPS tracker on a vehicle whose driver was unaware of the tracking through public streets. Rough historical equivalents, known to the drafters of the First Amendment and the Fourth Amendment (respectively, the constitutional provisions at issue in each case), could be construed, but their applicability was debatable. The question then becomes whether, in such situations, it is appropriate for judges to appeal to “higher-order principles.”

Yet Alito had reservations about one potential appeal in such instances: natural law. He argued that natural law was “not part of the picture” for the founders of constitutional originalism, and that invoking natural law has potential risks, including misuse or misinterpretation. He cited the argument of Justice Hugo Black, dissenting in Griswold v. Connecticut (which struck down a state contraception ban), erroneously describing the majority’s opinion as being rooted in natural law. Alito further noted that many rights have come to be known as natural rights “simply because they have widespread acceptance.” At the same time, there is an additional danger that, even though natural law is “based in reason, not in revelation,” invocations of natural law “would risk stirring up anti-Catholic prejudice” by mere affiliation. Finally, however, Alito argued that those who argue for a greater role of natural law in constitutional interpretation are engaging in a “kind of originalism” to the extent that they argue doing so would be consistent with the Framers’ intent.

Alito began his remarks modestly. Their depth revealed the seriousness of his intellect, even as his circumspection restrained his ambitions. The ultimate takeaway was a challenge to others, to rise to and participate in the conversation to which his own actions have so mightily contributed.

Jack Butler is submissions editor at National Review Online, media fellow for the Institute for Human Ecology, and a 2022–2023 Robert Novak Journalism Fellow at the Fund for American Studies.  
You have 1 article remaining.
You have 2 articles remaining.
You have 3 articles remaining.
You have 4 articles remaining.
You have 5 articles remaining.
Exit mobile version